ImageVerifierCode 换一换
格式:DOC , 页数:220 ,大小:1.29MB ,
资源ID:8667104      下载积分:10 金币
验证码下载
登录下载
邮箱/手机:
图形码:
验证码: 获取验证码
温馨提示:
支付成功后,系统会自动生成账号(用户名为邮箱或者手机号,密码是验证码),方便下次登录下载和查询订单;
特别说明:
请自助下载,系统不会自动发送文件的哦; 如果您已付费,想二次下载,请登录后访问:我的下载记录
支付方式: 支付宝    微信支付   
验证码:   换一换

开通VIP
 

温馨提示:由于个人手机设置不同,如果发现不能下载,请复制以下地址【https://www.zixin.com.cn/docdown/8667104.html】到电脑端继续下载(重复下载【60天内】不扣币)。

已注册用户请登录:
账号:
密码:
验证码:   换一换
  忘记密码?
三方登录: 微信登录   QQ登录  

开通VIP折扣优惠下载文档

            查看会员权益                  [ 下载后找不到文档?]

填表反馈(24小时):  下载求助     关注领币    退款申请

开具发票请登录PC端进行申请。


权利声明

1、咨信平台为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,收益归上传人(含作者)所有;本站仅是提供信息存储空间和展示预览,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容不做任何修改或编辑。所展示的作品文档包括内容和图片全部来源于网络用户和作者上传投稿,我们不确定上传用户享有完全著作权,根据《信息网络传播权保护条例》,如果侵犯了您的版权、权益或隐私,请联系我们,核实后会尽快下架及时删除,并可随时和客服了解处理情况,尊重保护知识产权我们共同努力。
2、文档的总页数、文档格式和文档大小以系统显示为准(内容中显示的页数不一定正确),网站客服只以系统显示的页数、文件格式、文档大小作为仲裁依据,个别因单元格分列造成显示页码不一将协商解决,平台无法对文档的真实性、完整性、权威性、准确性、专业性及其观点立场做任何保证或承诺,下载前须认真查看,确认无误后再购买,务必慎重购买;若有违法违纪将进行移交司法处理,若涉侵权平台将进行基本处罚并下架。
3、本站所有内容均由用户上传,付费前请自行鉴别,如您付费,意味着您已接受本站规则且自行承担风险,本站不进行额外附加服务,虚拟产品一经售出概不退款(未进行购买下载可退充值款),文档一经付费(服务费)、不意味着购买了该文档的版权,仅供个人/单位学习、研究之用,不得用于商业用途,未经授权,严禁复制、发行、汇编、翻译或者网络传播等,侵权必究。
4、如你看到网页展示的文档有www.zixin.com.cn水印,是因预览和防盗链等技术需要对页面进行转换压缩成图而已,我们并不对上传的文档进行任何编辑或修改,文档下载后都不会有水印标识(原文档上传前个别存留的除外),下载后原文更清晰;试题试卷类文档,如果标题没有明确说明有答案则都视为没有答案,请知晓;PPT和DOC文档可被视为“模板”,允许上传人保留章节、目录结构的情况下删减部份的内容;PDF文档不管是原文档转换或图片扫描而得,本站不作要求视为允许,下载前可先查看【教您几个在下载文档中可以更好的避免被坑】。
5、本文档所展示的图片、画像、字体、音乐的版权可能需版权方额外授权,请谨慎使用;网站提供的党政主题相关内容(国旗、国徽、党徽--等)目的在于配合国家政策宣传,仅限个人学习分享使用,禁止用于任何广告和商用目的。
6、文档遇到问题,请及时联系平台进行协调解决,联系【微信客服】、【QQ客服】,若有其他问题请点击或扫码反馈【服务填表】;文档侵犯商业秘密、侵犯著作权、侵犯人身权等,请点击“【版权申诉】”,意见反馈和侵权处理邮箱:1219186828@qq.com;也可以拔打客服电话:4009-655-100;投诉/维权电话:18658249818。

注意事项

本文(【伦理学】多元而冲突的价值.doc)为本站上传会员【pc****0】主动上传,咨信网仅是提供信息存储空间和展示预览,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容不做任何修改或编辑。 若此文所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知咨信网(发送邮件至1219186828@qq.com、拔打电话4009-655-100或【 微信客服】、【 QQ客服】),核实后会尽快下架及时删除,并可随时和客服了解处理情况,尊重保护知识产权我们共同努力。
温馨提示:如果因为网速或其他原因下载失败请重新下载,重复下载【60天内】不扣币。 服务填表

【伦理学】多元而冲突的价值.doc

1、Stocker, Michael , Guttag Professor of Ethics and Political Philosophy, Syracuse University, New York; Reader in Philosophy , La Trobe University, Melbourne Plural and Conflicting Values Print ISBN 0198240554, 1992 Summary Table of Contents     Introduction 1 PART I:   CONFLICT

2、1.   Dirty Hands and Ordinary Life 9 2.   Moral Immorality 37 3.   Dirty Hands and Conflicts of Values and of Desires in Aristotle's Ethics 51 4.   Moral Conflicts: What They Are and What They Show 85 PART II:   PLURALITY AND JUDGEMENT 5.   Courage, the Doctrine of the Mean, and th

3、e Possibility of Evaluative and Emotional Coherence 129 6.   Plurality and Choice 165 PART III:   PLURALITY AND CONFLICT 7.   Akrasia: The Unity of the Good, Commensurability, and Comparability 211 8.   Monism, Pluralism, and Conflict 241 PART IV:   MAXIMIZATION 9.   Maximizati

4、on: Some Conceptual Problems 281 10.   Maximization: Some Evaluative Problems 310   Bibliography 343   Indexes 351 end p.ix Introduction  show chapter abstract and keywords  hide chapter abstract and keywords Michael Stocker Neither plural values nor conflicting values can be un

5、derstood without understanding the other. And to understand ethics, we must understand both. They raise obvious and pressing problems in social and political theory. They also raise important problems within one person or one ethical theory—the locus of this work. Not surprisingly, then, they have r

6、eceived a considerable amount of attention recently—an amount of attention they fully deserve. So, I welcome the fact that they are now being studied. But I do not welcome many of the things claimed of them. Here are three representative assertions made about them recently: Plurality and conflict

7、 depend on and show a fragmentation of value and the disparate traditions that help make up our evaluative world and sensibility. A choice between plural values involves a conflict of values. Conflict requires plurality. Sometimes concluded from those three and sometimes offered on their own,

8、we find these four other recent and representative claims: Plural values are incommensurable and thus incomparable. There is no rational way to compare and choose between plural values, nor therefore to resolve conflicts. Plurality and conflict preclude sound judgement and decision, allowing o

9、nly vacillation and indecision, or simply plumping for one option or another. A rational ethics requires an evaluative and conflict-free monism. As I will argue, to understand plurality and conflict, these and similar claims must be rejected. And this is what I will do. There are, of course, pr

10、oblematic areas that involve plural values and conflicting values. And plurality and conflict can, of course, create problems. Moreover I see no theory, much less an algorithmic end p.1 one, which solves all these problems. But plurality and conflict are absolutely commonplace and generally unpro

11、blematic features of our everyday choice and action. They had thus better not be a bar to sound judgement, resolute and informed action, and a sound and rational ethics. Throughout, I will attempt to locate and correct those aspects of our ethical thought which have led—misled—us to think otherwise

12、 These include an overconcern with action-guiding act evaluations, such as 'ought' and 'duty' and a concomitant unconcern with other evaluations of acts, with evaluations that are not of acts, and quite generally with moral psychology. They also involve thinking of ethics, and especially of action-

13、guiding act evaluations, in terms of abstract rather than concrete value, i.e. asking only whether an act is the best act, rather than how and why it is good or best. They further involve an overdependence on maximizing theories of evaluation and rationality. I have divided the work into four Parts

14、 each of which considers one central topic. Part I—Chapters 1-4—focuses on the nature and problems of conflict. Part II—Chapters 5 and 6—focuses on the question of whether plural values preclude sound judgement. Part III—Chapters 7 and 8—discusses whether conflict requires plurality. Part IV—Chapte

15、rs 9 and 10—discusses maximization, with special emphasis on plurality. There is another way to divide these chapters—in terms of two emphases. One emphasis is on a particular issue. In Chapter 1, 'Dirty Hands and Ordinary Life', the issue is dirty hands—whether what is justified can be, none the l

16、ess, immoral. Chapter 2, 'Moral Immorality', considers a cognate issue, whether what is immoral can none the less be admirable. Three other chapters take up particular issues about conflict and plurality in Aristotle's ethics and moral psychology: Chapter 3, 'Dirty Hands and Conflicts of Values and

17、of Desires in Aristotle's Ethics', Chapter 5, 'Courage, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the Possibility of Evaluative and Emotional Coherence', and Chapter 7, 'Akrasia: The Unity of the Good, Commensurability, and Comparability'. The other emphasis is a more general and abstract consideration of a to

18、pic. Chapter 4, 'Moral Conflicts: What They Are and What They Show', takes up some general issues about conflict, which are raised particularly about dirty hands in Chapters 1 and 3. Chapter 6, 'Plurality and Choice', takes up the general issue of end p.2 whether plurality is an impediment to sou

19、nd choice. That issue is discussed in Chapter 5 in regard to Aristotle's account of courage. Chapter 8, 'Monism, Pluralism, and Conflict', discusses whether conflict, and especially whether rational conflict, requires plurality. This is discussed in regard to weakness of will in Chapter 7. Chapters

20、9 and 10, 'Maximization: Some Conceptual Problems' and 'Maximization: Some Evaluative Problems' take up some general issues about maximization which are raised in earlier chapters. The same topics are taken up more than once and in more than one way. Also each chapter is intended to stand on its ow

21、n. Thus there is some repetition. But as suggested in the Philebus (24e) it may be necessary, or at least useful, to say some things more than once to secure agreement and understanding. I rely frequently on Aristotle. As noted, three chapters are devoted to discussions of his ethics and moral psyc

22、hology, as are various sections of other chapters. My reasons for this have to do, in large part, with how I came to these problems. Although, early in my studies, I was convinced by G. E. Moore and W. D. Ross of the plurality and incommensurability of moral considerations, I did not consider plural

23、ity and incommensurability problematic. Two works on Aristotle's ethics, and an examination of a charge frequently made against his ethics, changed this. The first work, taken up in Chapter 5, argues that because courage involves plural and incommensurable values, victory and danger, and the proper

24、 emotions towards these, confidence and fear, there are severe problems in seeing how courage can involve a mean—either in one's concern with these values or in one's emotions. Since they do not shade into each other, how can too much of the one be too little of the other, and how, then, can there b

25、e a mean of, or between, them? As I will be concerned to argue, this problem can be solved by seeing how incommensurable values and emotions can fuse into complex wholes of disparate and incommensurable values and emotions, and can thus be assessed as lying or not lying in a mean. This has direct a

26、pplication to the more recent and quite general worry that where we have incommensurable values, sound comparisons and sound judgement will be impossible—that there is no sound way to compare unlikes with unlikes. This general worry is taken up in Chapter 6, which shows that virtually all our choice

27、s concern plural and incommensurable considerations and that we end p.3 are, none the less, able to make sound judgements—by fusing these considerations into complex wholes of disparate and incommensurable elements. The second work on Aristotle, discussed in Chapter 7, argues that coherent akras

28、ia, weakness of will, requires plural values. This work was concerned to show how Aristotle's pluralism could thus easily allow for akrasia, whereas the monism found in the Protagoras makes akrasia conceptually impossible. This easily generalizes to the view many now have, taken up in Chapter 8, tha

29、t conflict quite generally requires plurality. As the leading idea can be put, 'There could be no conflict between two options if, as one sees, they have the very same attractive features. Thus, conflict requires difference.' As I will be concerned to show, both in regard to Aristotle and more gene

30、rally, this linking of conflict and plurality depends on a seriously mistaken understanding of reason and reasons for acting and of the role of affectivity and emotion in action. I will, however, argue that there are very close connections between plurality and conflict, and especially rational conf

31、lict—and that we may have to characterize each in terms of the other. The charge made against Aristotle's ethics is that he leaves no room for moral conflicts in general or dirty hands in particular—i.e. cases where no matter what one does, one will do something wrong. We are told that this is so b

32、ecause he thought his good people could resolve all issues and act resolutely, no matter how difficult the situation. Some contemporary philosophers see this as a simple implication of his and Plato's somewhat different doctrine of the unity of virtues. But conflicts—because they involve doing what

33、is wrong, no matter what one does—show that such a person is at best an unrealizable ideal. As I will be concerned to argue in Chapter 3, this is a mistaken account of Aristotle's ethics and moral psychology. His good people may well be able to resolve issues and act resolutely in virtually any sit

34、uation. None the less, as shown by what he says about mixed acts—those acts that somehow are both voluntary and not—he recognizes that it is possible even for a good person to have no choice but to do what is wrong. As he says at the beginning of Nicomachean Ethics 3, a person may be able to save hi

35、s family from a tyrant only by doing a base or shameful act. This, however, allows that such a person can see clearly what end p.4 is to be done and will act resolutely. In the case at hand, the person should save his family and he should do this resolutely—despite the fact that he will have to

36、do what is base. Thus, there is conflict. It is not a conflict of indecision and vacillation, but a conflict within a single moral appreciation of what is to be done. The conflict is within the one complex whole composed of disparate and incommensurable elements. Such conflict is best understood in

37、moral psychological terms and as having to do with the conflicting elements of a situation that are seen and felt as conflicting, even where the agent also sees clearly what is to be done and resolutely takes that course of action. This line of thought is also pursued in Chapter 1 in regard to dirt

38、y hands, and in Chapters 2 and 4 in regard to conflicts more generally. Here I argue that to understand conflicts—and not to see them as posing serious, even catastrophic, problems for ethics and ethical theory—we cannot approach them as our contemporary ethical theories more or less force us to do.

39、 That is, we cannot see them simply as involving incompossible action-guiding act evaluations, telling us at once to do and not do a given act. Rather, we must recognize that there are other important evaluations of acts than action-guiding ones. And we must also see that there is more to evaluate t

40、han acts. One way to get at these other areas is, as already suggested, via a study of the moral psychology of conflict. For this will help us see that there are properly conflicting ways to appreciate the complex wholes that we are faced with when we decide and act, especially where there are confl

41、icts. My approach to plurality and conflict—both my past approach and also as I now think of the issues—is thus directed by my concern with Aristotle's ethics and moral psychology. I find this entirely natural, since, as I see matters, plurality and conflict are at the heart of his ethics and moral

42、 psychology. And, also as I see matters, if we keep our problems with plurality and conflict in mind while examining his treatment of them, we will come to a better understanding of both our problems and our ethics and moral psychology, as well as his. (Much the same applies to Plato, to whom I also

43、 turn.) However, I know that many do not share my appreciation of Aristotle—especially on these topics. I would be pleased if my chapters on Aristotle move them towards my view. But there are some who find it distracting to discuss a contemporary or abstract end p.5 issue by means of a historica

44、l text or philosopher. It is partly for this reason that, despite the repetition involved, I have tried to make each of the chapters self-contained. Those who want to pursue the contemporary and abstract issues about plurality and conflict without recourse to Aristotle can simply omit Chapters 3, 5,

45、 and 7. Those who want to concentrate on Aristotle can omit the others. For my own part, I still find it best to think about these topics together. end p.6 Part I Conflict end p.7 end p.8 1 Dirty Hands and Ordinary Life  show chapter abstract and keywords  hide chapter abstract and keywords

46、 Michael Stocker Can there be acts of dirty hands—acts that are justified, even obligatory, but none the less wrong and shameful? To borrow an example from Michael Walzer, can it be justified, even obligatory, for an official to torture someone to force him to tell where his fellows have hidden

47、a time bomb among the innocent populace? And if, as Walzer suggests, it can be justified, even obligatory, to do this, can it also be wrong and shameful? This question has recently attracted much attention, but little agreement. 1  1 Here is a partial, chronological list: M. Merleau-Ponty, Humanis

48、m and Terror (Boston: Beacon Press, 1971); T. Nagel, 'War and Massacre', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1 (1972) 123-44; M. Walzer, 'Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands', Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (1973) 160-80; R. Brandt, 'Utilitarianism and the Rules of War', Philosophy and Public A

49、ffairs 1 (1972) 145-65; R. M. Hare, 'Rules of War and Moral Reasoning', Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972), 166-81; B. Williams, 'Ethical Consistency' and 'Consistency and Realism', Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), and 'Conflicts of Values', Moral Luck (Cambrid

50、ge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); B. Williams and J. J. C. Smart, Utilitarianism, For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973); T. McConnell, 'Moral Dilemmas and Consistency in Ethics', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 8 (1978), 269-87; R. Marcus, 'Moral Dilemmas and Ethical Con

移动网页_全站_页脚广告1

关于我们      便捷服务       自信AI       AI导航        抽奖活动

©2010-2025 宁波自信网络信息技术有限公司  版权所有

客服电话:4009-655-100  投诉/维权电话:18658249818

gongan.png浙公网安备33021202000488号   

icp.png浙ICP备2021020529号-1  |  浙B2-20240490  

关注我们 :微信公众号    抖音    微博    LOFTER 

客服