收藏 分销(赏)

《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课.doc

上传人:天**** 文档编号:3893976 上传时间:2024-07-23 格式:DOC 页数:29 大小:102.54KB
下载 相关 举报
《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课.doc_第1页
第1页 / 共29页
《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课.doc_第2页
第2页 / 共29页
《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课.doc_第3页
第3页 / 共29页
《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课.doc_第4页
第4页 / 共29页
《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课.doc_第5页
第5页 / 共29页
点击查看更多>>
资源描述

1、 This is a course about justice and we begin with a story. Suppose youre the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour. And at the end of the track, you notice five workers working on the track. You try to stop but you cant, your brakes dont work. Y

2、ou feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all die. Lets assume you know that for sure. And so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the end of that track, there is one worker working on the track. Your st

3、eering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five. Heres our first question: whats the right thing to do? What would you do? Lets take a poll. How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? Raise your hands. How ma

4、ny wouldnt? How many would go straight ahead? Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. A handful of people would, the vast majority would turn. Lets hear first, now we need to begin to investigate the reasons why you think its the right thing to do. Lets begin with those in the m

5、ajority who would turn to go onto the side track. Why would you do it? What would be your reason? Whos willing to volunteer a reason? Go ahead. Stand up. Because it cant be right to kill five people when you can only kill one person instead. It wouldnt be right to kill five if you could kill one per

6、son instead. Thats a good reason. Who else? Does everybody agree with that reason? Go ahead. Well I was thinking its the same reason on 9/11 with regard to the people who flew the plane into the Pennsylvania field as heroes because they chose to kill the people on the plane and not kill more people

7、in big buildings. So the principle there was the same on 9/11. Its a tragic circumstance but better to kill one so that five can live, is that the reason most of you had, those of you who would turn? Yes? Lets hear now from those in the minority, those who wouldnt turn. Yes. Well, I think thats the

8、same type of mentality that justifies genocide and totalitarianism. In order to save one type of race, you wipe out the other. So what would you do in this case? You would, to avoid the horrors of genocide, you would crash into the five and kill them? Presumably, yes. You would?-Yeah. Okay. Who else

9、? Thats a brave answer. Thank you. Lets consider another trolley car case and see whether those of you in the majority want to adhere to the principle: better that one should die so that five should live. This time youre not the driver of the trolley car, youre an onlooker. Youre standing on a bridg

10、e overlooking a trolley car track. And down the track comes a trolley car, at the end of the track are five workers, the brakes dont work, the trolley car is about to careen into the five and kill them. And now, youre not the driver, you really feel helpless until you notice standing next to you, le

11、aning over the bridge is a very fat man. And you could give him a shove. He would fall over the bridge onto the track right in the way of the trolley car. He would die but he would spare the five. Now, how many would push the fat man over the bridge? Raise your hand.How many wouldnt? Most people wou

12、ldnt. Heres the obvious question. What became of the principle better to save five lives even if it means sacrificing one? What became of the principlethat almost everyone endorsed in the first case? I need to hear from someone who was in the majority in both cases. How do you explain the difference

13、 between the two? Yes. The second one, I guess, involves an active choice of pushing a person downwhich I guess that person himself would otherwise not have been involved in the situation at all. And so to choose on his behalf, I guess, to involve him in something that he otherwise would have escape

14、d is, I guess, more than what you have in the first case where the three parties, the driver and the two sets of workers, are already, I guess, in the situation. But the guy working, the one on the track off to the side, he didnt choose to sacrifice his life any more than the fat man did, did he? Th

15、ats true, but he was on the tracks and. This guy was on the bridge.Go ahead, you can come back if you want. All right. Its a hard question. You did well. You did very well. Its a hard question.Who else can find a way of reconciling the reaction of the majority in these two cases? Yes. Well, I guess

16、in the first case where you have the one worker and the five, its a choice between those two and you have to make a certain choice and people are going to die because of the trolley car, not necessarily because of your direct actions. The trolley car is a runaway thingand youre making a split second

17、 choice. Whereas pushing the fat man over is an actual act of murder on your part. You have control over that whereas you may not have control over the trolley car. So I think its a slightly different situation. All right, who has a reply? Thats good. Who has a way? Who wants to reply? Is that a way

18、 out of this? I dont think thats a very good reason because you choose to- either way you have to choose who dies because you either choose to turn and kill the person, which is an act of conscious thought to turn, or you choose to push the fat man over which is also an active, conscious action. So

19、either way, youre making a choice. Do you want to reply? Im not really sure that thats the case. It just still seems kind of different. The act of actually pushing someone over onto the tracks and killing him, you are actually killing him yourself. Youre pushing him with your own hands.Youre pushing

20、 him and thats different than steering something that is going to cause death into another. You know, it doesnt really sound right saying it now. No, no. Its good. Its good.Whats your name? Andrew. Andrew. Let me ask you this question, Andrew. Yes. Suppose standing on the bridge next to the fat man,

21、 I didnt have to push him, suppose he was standing over a trap door that I could open by turning a steering wheel like that. Would you turn? For some reason, that still just seems more wrong. Right? I mean, maybe if you accidentally like leaned into the steering wheel or something like that. But. Or

22、 say that the car is hurtling towards a switch that will drop the trap. Then I could agree with that. Thats all right. Fair enough. It still seems wrong in a way that it doesnt seem wrong in the first case to turn, you say. And in another way, I mean, in the first situation youre involved directly w

23、ith the situation. In the second one, youre an onlooker as well. All right. -So you have the choice of becoming involved or not by pushing the fat man. All right. Lets forget for the moment about this case.Thats good. Lets imagine a different case. This time youre a doctor in an emergency room and s

24、ix patients come to you. Theyve been in a terrible trolley car wreck.Five of them sustain moderate injuries,one is severely injured, you could spend all day caring for the one severely injured victim but in that time, the five would die. Or you could look after the five, restore them to health but d

25、uring that time, the one severely injured person would die. How many would save the five? Now as the doctor, how many would save the one? Very few people, just a handful of people. Same reason, I assume.One life versus five? Now consider another doctor case. This time, youre a transplant surgeon and

26、 you have five patients, each in desperate need of an organ transplant in order to survive.One needs a heart, one a lung, one a kidney,one a liver, and the fifth a pancreas.And you have no organ donors.You are about to see them die.And then it occurs to you that in the next room theres a healthy guy

27、 who came in for a check-up. And hes you like that and hes taking a nap, you could go in very quietly,yank out the five organs, that person would die, but you could save the five. How many would do it?Anyone? How many? Put your hands up if you would do it.Anyone in the balcony? I would.You would? Be

28、 careful,dont lean over too much. How many wouldnt? All right. What do you say? Speak up in the balcony, you who would yank out the organs. Why? Id actually like to explore a slightly alternate possibility of just taking the one of the five who needs an organ who dies first and using their four heal

29、thy organs to save the other four. Thats a pretty good idea. Thats a great idea except for the fact that you just wrecked the philosophical point. Lets step back from these stories and these arguments to notice a couple of things about the way the arguments have begun to unfold. Certain moral princi

30、ples have already begun to emerge from the discussions weve had. And lets consider what those moral principles look like. The first moral principle that emerged in the discussion said the right thing to do, the moral thing to do depends on the consequences that will result from your action. At the e

31、nd of the day, better that five should live even if one must die. Thats an example of consequentialist moral reasoning. Consequentialist moral reasoning locates morality in the consequences of an act, in the state of the world that will result from the thing you do. But then we went a little further

32、, we considered those other cases and people werent so sure about consequentialist moral reasoning. When people hesitated to push the fat man over the bridge or to yank out the organs of the innocent patient, people gestured toward reasons having to do with the intrinsic quality of the act itself, c

33、onsequences be what they may. People were reluctant. People thought it was just wrong, categorically wrong, to kill a person, an innocent person, even for the sake of saving five lives. At least people thought that in the second version of each story we considered. So this points to a second categor

34、ical way of thinking about moral reasoning.Categorical moral reasoning locates morality in certain absolute moral requirements, certain categorical duties and rights, regardless of the consequences. Were going to explore in the days and weeks to come the contrast between consequentialist and categor

35、ical moral principles. The most influential example of consequential moral reasoning is utilitarianism, a doctrine invented by Jeremy Bentham, the 18th century English political philosopher. The most important philosopher of categorical moral reasoning is the 18th century German philosopher Immanuel

36、 Kant. So we will look at those two different modes of moral reasoning, assess them, and also consider others. If you look at the syllabus, youll notice that we read a number of great and famous books, books by Aristotle, John Locke, Immanuel Kant, John Stewart Mill, and others. Youll notice too fro

37、m the syllabus sthat we dont only read these books; we also take up contemporary, political, and legal controversies that raise philosophical questions. We will debate equality and inequality, affirmative action, free speech versus hate speech, same sex marriage, military conscription, a range of pr

38、actical questions. Why? Not just to enliven these abstract and distant books but to make clear, to bring out whats at stake in our everyday lives, including our political lives, for philosophy. And so we will read these books and we will debate these issues, and well see how each informs and illumin

39、ates the other. This may sound appealing enough, but here I have to issue a warning. And the warning is this,to read these books in this way as an exercise in self knowledge, to read them in this way carries certain risks, risks that are both personal and political, risks that every student of polit

40、ical philosophy has known. These risks spring from the fact that philosophy teaches us and unsettles usby confronting us with what we already know. Theres an irony. The difficulty of this course consists in the fact that it teaches what you already know. It works by taking what we know from familiar

41、 unquestioned settings and making it strange. Thats how those examples worked, the hypotheticals with which we began, with their mix of playfulness and sobriety. Its also how these philosophical books work. Philosophy estranges us from the familiar, not by supplying new information but by inviting a

42、nd provoking a new way of seeing but, and heres the risk, once the familiar turns strange, its never quite the same again. Self knowledge is like lost innocence, however unsettling you find it; it can never be un-thought or un-known. What makes this enterprise difficult but also riveting is that mor

43、al and political philosophy is a story and you dont know where the story will lead. But what you do know is that the story is about you. Those are the personal risks. Now what of the political risks? One way of introducing a course like this would be to promise you that by reading these books and de

44、bating these issues, you will become a better, more responsible citizen; you will examine the presuppositions of public policy, you will hone your political judgment, you will become a more effective participant in public affairs. But this would be a partial and misleading promise. Political philoso

45、phy, for the most part, hasnt worked that way. You have to allow for the possibility that political philosophy may make you a worse citizen rather than a better one or at least a worse citizen before it makes you a better one, and thats because philosophy is a distancing, even debilitating, activity

46、. And you see this, going back to Socrates, theres a dialogue, the Gorgias, in which one of Socrates friends, Callicles, tries to talk him out of Philosophizing. Callicles tells Socrates Philosophy is a pretty toy if one indulges in it with moderation at the right time of life. But if one pursues it

47、 further than one should, it is absolute ruin. Take my advice, Callicles says, abandon argument. Learn the accomplishments of active life, take for your models not those people who spend their time on these petty quibbles but those who have a good livelihood and reputation and many other blessings.

48、So Callicles is really saying to Socrates Quit philosophizing, get real, go to business school. And Callicles did have a point. He had a point because philosophy distances us from conventions, from established assumptions, and from settled beliefs. Those are the risks, personal and political. And in

49、 the face of these risks, there is a characteristic evasion. The name of the evasion is skepticism, its the idea well, it goes something like this we didnt resolve once and for all either the cases or the principles we were arguing when we began and if Aristotle and Locke and Kant and Mill havent solved these questions after all of these years, who are we to think that we, here in Sanders Theatre, over the course of a semester, can

展开阅读全文
部分上传会员的收益排行 01、路***(¥15400+),02、曲****(¥15300+),
03、wei****016(¥13200+),04、大***流(¥12600+),
05、Fis****915(¥4200+),06、h****i(¥4100+),
07、Q**(¥3400+),08、自******点(¥2400+),
09、h*****x(¥1400+),10、c****e(¥1100+),
11、be*****ha(¥800+),12、13********8(¥800+)。
相似文档                                   自信AI助手自信AI助手
百度文库年卡

猜你喜欢                                   自信AI导航自信AI导航
搜索标签

当前位置:首页 > 包罗万象 > 大杂烩

移动网页_全站_页脚广告1

关于我们      便捷服务       自信AI       AI导航        获赠5币

©2010-2024 宁波自信网络信息技术有限公司  版权所有

客服电话:4008-655-100  投诉/维权电话:4009-655-100

gongan.png浙公网安备33021202000488号   

icp.png浙ICP备2021020529号-1  |  浙B2-20240490  

关注我们 :gzh.png    weibo.png    LOFTER.png 

客服